Judgments in which an individual gives free play to 'er
own way of seeing, hearing, smelling, tasting and touching
things in the outside world are founded upon mere feelings
rather than upon interpersonal considerations and are thus
subjective. While associating and processing the sensory reactions
in the body's parts and organs, the feelings developing in
such an individual are feelings of love or liking, of anger,
hate or disliking. 'E may anticipate danger and pain, possibly
accompanied by fear; or protection and pleasure, possibly
accompanied by a feeling of security. The same stimulus may
induce love in one individual and hate in another; or it may
induce a feeling of security in the former individual and fear
in the latter one. Things which are related for the one, because
'e is used to associate them while liking or disliking them all,
are completely unrelated for the other, because 'e is not used
to associate them. Even when people's (or their bodies')
feelings are not opposed, they can still differ considerably in
intensity: what induces mere liking in A may induce a deeply
felt love in B; or what induces mere disliking in C may induce a
deeply felt hatred in D. This lack of interindividual (or
'interpersonal', or 'intersubjective') continuity is precisely
what characterizes subjectivity.
It is not utterances in which a person gives free rein to 'er
own feelings which are subjective in that they are, or could be,
illusory. When someone says that 'e 'imself likes or dislikes a
certain sight or smell, for instance, there is not any reason to
assume that what 'e says would not be true. And if 'e also says
it to explain or justify 'er own, personal behavior, there is
not any reason to assume that 'er feelings would not be relevant
in that context. When we speak of "judgments", however, we do
not refer to mere utterances but to opinions, assertions or
formal utterances. To say that one likes a certain type of fruit
may be true and relevant, but it could hardly be termed "a
judgment". The subjectivity of such an utterance is not the kind
of subjectivity to be concerned about, for the distinction
between subjectivity and objectivity just does not act a part
for utterances of which the scope is purely individual.
Even when the scope of an utterance is not purely individual,
the utterance may still be subjective when it applies to each
individual separately. For example, we all like babanas stands
for a conjunction of the type A likes bananas and B likes
bananas and ... . However, bananas taste good or bananas are
healthy are not mere utterances but judgments of a scope
which is not purely individual, and it is such judgments which
have to be objective, that is, interindividually reliable. To be
reliable they cannot be exclusively based on the speaker or
writer's own feelings or experiences, because other people's
feelings and experiences may have a different intensity, or may
even be opposed. One particular human being's or group of human
beings' sensory reactions does not establish a nonpersonal or
supra-individual fact. To obtain an objective judgment the same
stimulus has to evoke the same reaction in all who can sense
this stimulus. This is not to say that the universal frame of
reference (of all individuals which can sense a certain kind of
stimulus) could not be immeasurably large and even unknown so
far as other planets or galaxies are concerned. In practise
human beings are forced to confine themselves to a relatively
small frame of reference. This does not at all have to discredit
a judgment so long as it is realized and expressed that the
judgment in question is solely valid for the same frame of
reference. Within such a smaller frame, judgments can still be
interindividually reliable. To be an objective statement,
bananas are healthy, for instance, must at least specify for
what species and age-groups they are healthy and under what
conditions (such as the number to be eaten in a certain period).
Subjectivity is wrong when it involves utterances or ideas
which are perhaps reliable and justifiable for one individual or
for one particular group of individuals, but which are considered
binding, or demanded to be binding, for other individuals as
well, or for individuals not belonging to that particular group.
There is a confusion of scopes: the scope of the judgment's
reliability and justifiability is different from that of its
application. In other words, the judgment is not relevant in the
practical context concerned. To be objective a judgment has to
be both true and relevant in the context in which it is applied.
Objectivity is therefore not simply a matter of being
intersubjectively observable, verifiable or falsifiable. Or, if it
is, such would not be a reason to regard it as normatively
superior to subjectivity. It is only normatively superior when
it involves truth instead of falsehood, and relevance instead of
irrelevance.
Judgments are not only objective because they are reliable
for the same framework as the one in which they are used, they
can also be objective when the framework in which they are used
is much bigger. This is the case when the basis of the judgment
is restricted to the past and the present, but when there is no
reason to assume that it will not be true in the future as well.
It is an objective view (held true by scientists) to believe
that apples will continue to fall off trees in the future, altho
this cannot now be observed, and altho this cannot now be
verified or falsified. It would even be arbitrary or 'subjective'
to believe that apples did and do solely happen to fall
off trees in the past or present (unless it can be made
plausible that human civilization is not capable of improving
drastically and will eventually lead to the destruction of a
great part or of all life on Earth, inclusive of apple trees).
Strictly speaking, it can indeed not be proved that ground-world
events which were 'always' conjoined, or 'always' succeeded
each other in the past, will continue to be conjoined or will
continue to succeed each other in the future. But if two of such
events are not believed to be conjoined or to succeed each
other anymore in the future, the onus is on the one who does
not assume that the conjunction or the succession will remain
unaltered, to prove that such a discontinuity is to be expected.
For the one who must show that the assumption of discontinuity
(such as that the Sun will not rise anymore tomorrow) is more
plausible than the assumption of sameness or continuity (that
the Sun will rise as usual tomorrow), it is imperative to bring
forward relevant factors overlooked before or relevant recent
changes.
The objective attitude in the factual or modal spheres can
and must be extended to the normative sphere. In this sphere it
cannot be proved either that, for example, people are 'equal',
that is, should be treated in the same way in similar situations.
But if two persons are not believed to be equal, the
onus is on the one who does not assume equality between people
to prove that a different treatment of persons in similar
situations is relevant. This is what both the norm of inclusivity
and the norm of interpersonal equality demand from us. In
this respect, too, normative theories like inclusivism and
relevantist egalitarianism turn out to be not more and not less
objective than factual-modal ones like the theory on cause and
effect.