1.4 |
ATTRIBUTES AS ULTIMATE CONSTITUENTS |
1.4.1 |
SIMPLEX AND COMPLEX THINGS IN DIFFERENT
DOMAINS |
It has been pointed out (in
1.2.1) that for every
relation there are one or more derelativized one-place predicates.
If A looks at B, there is a relation of looking between A
and B, directed from A towards B. Thing A, then, has the
property of looking-at-something, or simply looking, and B has
the property of being-looked-at. A is at the fundament of the
relation and performs the act of looking. (Looking is something
else than receiving reflected beams of light.) We shall assume
that the active form looking(-at-something) represents a real
attribute. B, which is at the terminus of the relation, does
not perform anything, and there is no need to assume that it has
any real attribute because of its being looked at.
Being-looked-at and other passive forms stand as such for
pseudo-attributes. In diagrams where we show nonprimitive relations
between things as lines connecting these things, there is no
need to show the corresponding, existing one-place predicate(s)
separately (inside the closed curve): altho not wrong, it would
be superfluous.
It has also been pointed out that a relation between basic
things is a relation between attributes in the attributive
interpretation of formal systems. If there is such a relation,
then at least one of these related attributes must have a
derelativized one-place predicate itself. But in the first
domain of discourse such an attribute has no elements because it
is a basic thing in this domain. Therefore it cannot be at the
fundament of a relation with something else at all. It could be
at the terminus of a relation tho as this does not require the
attribute to have a real one-place predicate itself. When an
attribute is said to have attributes itself, and when an
attribute is said to have relations in which it is not just at
the terminus, it is treated as a nonbasic thing, a thing with
several elements itself, in another domain of discourse. The
relations between those attributes belong to that domain of
discourse too, that is, not to the domain in which one speaks of
relations between nonattributive objects. Whereas the latter
relations are primary, the former are secondary. And
whereas attributes which are not attributes of any other (kind
of) attribute are primary, the attributes of those attributes
are secondary attributes. All of them are primary and secondary
predicates.
Just like in the objectualist interpretation, a predicate of
a predicate of order n is itself a predicate of order n+1. This
does not apply to the primitive having(-as-an-element), because
this is a 'relation' inherent in the hierarchical structure
itself. Like being and existing it is of all orders, or rather
of no order in particular. The same applies to the primitive
'relation' of identity, which is purely conceptual and neither
ontic nor of any particular order either. Identity solely plays
a role in the description of reality, not in nonpropositional
reality itself. Identity statements cannot express a relation
between different things in reality, because, trivially,
everything is identical to itself and to nothing else.
Predicates have only higher-order (nonprimitive) predicates.
They do not have component parts, of whatever order they might
be. So every predicate of order n is an ontic set of predicates
of order n+1. In the same way as a 'really elementary', that is,
simplicial, particle is a set of primary attributes, a primary
attribute is itself a set of secondary attributes, a secondary
attribute a set of tertiary attributes, and so on. And like in
the objectualist interpretation there is in principle no end to
this hierarchy. Those who despise infinity should bear in mind
that this hierarchy is an abstract, conceptual structure and in
no way forces us to accept the existence of infinite sets of
concrete things.
As a basic thing a predicate belongs to one domain of
discourse, and as a set of predicates to another one, that is,
the next domain. Thus there are (basic) things in the one domain
which are identical to (nonbasic) things in the next domain.
This identity of things across the border of domains can be
represented by means of a line interrupted by a special identity
symbol (=), as indicated in figure I.1.4.1.1.
It is now clear why it may seem that a relation between
primary attributes exists in the first domain of discourse. The
explanation is that the relation exists between two nonbasic
things of the second domain which are both found as basic things
in the first domain as well. The relation itself is secondary,
however, and corresponds to a secondary one-place predicate
found inside at least one of the primary attributes in the
second domain of discourse. Figure I.1.4.1.2 gives some examples
of primary, pseudoprimary and secondary relations between
and with primary attributes. (By way of clarity the relational
attributes are shown extra as a separate attribute besides the
relations themselves.)
In the attributivist terminology a universe of discourse is
the totality of all hierarchically ordered domains involved in a
particular communication. The ultimate constituents of the first
domain of this universe are primary attributes, those of primary
attributes and all other things of the second domain secondary
attributes, those of secondary attributes and all other things
of the third domain tertiary attributes, and so on. Hence, the
ultimate constituents of all domains are attributes, and those
of a particular universe of discourse the attributes of the
highest domain in the hierarchy.
The simplex particles and the predicates in a universe of
discourse are all simplex things, that is, things which have
no extensional elements and which cannot present themselves by
means of component parts. They are sets of predicates which
exist in reality as a thing -- according to our typification in
section 1.3.2 as a thing of type 2. All things of
a higher type we shall call "complex things". Simplex and
complex things belong to the same domain as the attributes of the highest
order they have belong to. (Attributes of a lower order are components.)
Hence, a simplicial particle belongs to the first
domain, altho it could be represented as a set of sets of
secondary attributes in a universe of discourse which would
include the second domain too. If we allowed this, however,
only its 'parts' would have attributes and relations, not the
thing itself. Since a simplicial particle must have attributes
and relations of itself, it does not belong to the domain of
secondary attributes. On the other hand, a complex thing with a
primary attribute does belong to the second domain, if it
contains one or more secondary attributes as well. Its primary
attribute is, then, not an attribute in the sense of a basic thing,
but a component part.
Some might have expected that our distinction between parts
(as nonpredicative elements) and attributes (as basic, predicative
elements) is a distinction only to be found in the physical
world. They might have believed such a distinction to be
inappropriate to the general framework of an ontology. But our
example of a complex thing in the domain of secondary attributes
proves that this objection is wrong, for complexity of this sort
exists as much in the abstract world as it exists in the
concrete or physical world. The very recognition of this
complexity is an absolute prerequisite to understanding the
structures in both these worlds. It is of paramount importance
to realize at this stage that the universe does not only
encompass material things, with or without related things and
attributes, but that it also encompasses complex systems of
nonprimary attributes. The development of one of the two paradigmatic
components of our weltanschauung itself will depend on this insight.
|