1.5.3 |
HAVING AND PART IN A STRICT AND
IN A LOOSE SENSE |
A table is not simply the set of a number of particular
legs, or a particular stump and a particular board, altho it is
made up of them. Three or more legs at one place and a board
somewhere else do not yet constitute a real table; maybe they
can or could constitute one. To actually be a table, more is
needed and this more of every table is, or is found in, its
attributive predicament. 'Mereologists' may talk about the
different parts of the table and even wonder whether they are
essential or not, while at the same time defining this table as
a mere extensionality. (Mereological essentialists claim that
all or certain parts are always essential to their whole.)
When running into difficulties they may distinguish 'popular
parts' for the ordinary or loose sense of part from
'philosophical parts' when speaking of "parts" in a strict sense.
In a 'creative' bout of supernaturalist elation a realm of 'entia
successiva' (things which are such that at any moment of their
existence something other than themselves serves as their stand
in and does duty for them), 'entia per alio' (things which
derive all their attributes from other things which do duty for
them) and 'entia per se' ('real things') may be hypostatized.
But ordinary talk about wholes and parts cannot be that
inadequate, even tho one of the issues, that of things remaining
the same (or identical) thru time, is a delicate one.
Theories which cannot tackle the ordinary language of wholes,
parts and attributes without taking refuge in a thicket of
ethereal entities just don't ring true. This is not to say that
they would be wrong or uninteresting in every respect. For
example, it does turn out very fruitful to draw a distinction
between a strict and a loose sense of the words part and
having, also in our nonmereological framework. The difference
is that it is a very straightforward distinction here which can
be easily defined in set-theoretical terms. For a clear understanding
we must in the first instance reject in our case
the axiom that if X is a part of Y and Y is a part of Z, then X
is also a part of Z. If parts are genuine wholes themselves (and
recognized as 'individuals'), then a part X of Y is, strictly
speaking, no part of Z, even if Y is part of Z. (The axiom
itself is the expression of a mereological conception of wholes
and parts.) A part of a part of Z is something else than a part
of Z, just as a parent of a parent of P is not (necessarily) a
parent of P, and just as an utterance about an utterance about a
fact F is not (necessarily) an utterance about F itself. At the
same time it cannot be denied that one often calls a part of a
part of A also "a part of A", or an utterance about an utterance
about B also "an utterance about B" (and a friend of a friend of
C also "a friend of C"?) in a loose sense. Especially when the
division into parts, and also subjects, is vague or quite
arbitrary the loose usage may suffice for the purpose of the
conversation. But whether the term part is employed in a
strict or in a loose sense, Y is never a part of X, if X is a
part of Y (as another axiom reads). This is because in both
cases part only refers to proper parts, not to wholes which
would be 'their own part'.
The appeal of the distinction between the strict and the
loose meanings of part and having is that it provides us
with an alternative to extensional mereology (having refused to
accept total mereology in any case). The distinction allows us
to do away with the very complicated 'fusions' to which not only
the parts of the whole belong but also the parts of parts and
collections of parts, or of parts of parts, and so on. This is
not a very practical, accurate picture because, for example,
somebody does not have a hand and five fingers in addition to
that hand; that person('s body) has a hand and that hand has
in turn five fingers (granted that the number is correct). It
follows from this that also that person has those five fingers,
but then in a looser sense of having.
The part-whole configuration and the transition from a strict
to an ever looser sense of having can be well demonstrated
particularly with regard to persons. It is therefore high time
now to see how these peculiar entities which no adequate
ontology may ignore or neglect can be portrayed by means of our
own conceptual apparatus.
|