A predicate which a thing would not have, if it were not
thought, talked or written about by the person(s) thinking,
talking or writing, does not determine its character in any way.
Such a predicate is merely a product of the person's or our
conception (perhaps even of our imagination) and must not be
considered a determinative predicate of the thing in question.
So far as the relation of conceiving between a person and the
thing itself is concerned, this is an asymmetrical relation with
the person thinking, talking or writing at the fundament, and
with this person having the attribute which results from
derelativizing the relation. Quite a few traditional languages
distinguish feminine, neuter and masculine genders, but
this does not mean that any of these genders is determinative
for the thing it is attributed to. Also the mere fact that a
thing is thought, talked or written about now, does not mean
that it does exist now or did ever exist at all, for being
thought about, being talked about and being written
about are purely conceptual predicates. When people are
'macarized', that is, called "happy", they do not have or get
any determinative predicate on the basis of being macarized, and it
certainly does not make them happy. It is solely the people
macarizing who have a real, determinative predicate in this way.
(Altho for certain religious devotees dutifully macarizing
themselves both assertions may seem to hold.)
Predicate expressions which do not designate any existing
attribute or relation but which are determinative nevertheless
refer to '(determinative) pseudopredicates'. If P is a
determinative predicate which is no pseudopredicate, then not
having P is a privative (pseudo)predicate.
Privative expressions predicate privation or absence of an attribute or
relation and thus stand for nothing. They replace a certain expression or
part thereof in the particular language applied. When we define
abstract as not concrete, for instance, the statement that a
certain thing is abstract replaces the statement that it is not
concrete, that is, that it lacks the attribute of being
concrete. Being abstract is, then, not a proper attribute. Similarly,
when something is dead, it does not mean that it has a
proper attribute of being dead, it means that it does not have
the attribute of living, that it is deprived of life. Being-dead
is therefore a pseudo-attribute and, strictly speaking, death
does not exist. In the same way, blindness is a privative
pseudo-attribute where blind is a synonym of sightless.
Altho prefixes like a-, non- and un- may be
called "privatives" by linguists, predicate terms which begin with one
of these affixes need not refer to privative predicates by any
manner of means. For example, unhappiness has the same ontological
status as happiness: they are opposites of each other. The
one predicate is not 'more privative' than the other, just like
hatred is not 'more privative' than love, and vice versa. The
fact that unhappiness was not given a positive or affirmative
name in this language, like happiness or hatred, does in no way
determine its existence or nonexistence.
Certain predicates designated by predicative expressions are
improper, not because the expression does not denote any
existing predicate, but rather because it does not denote one
particular, existing predicate. A class of such improper predicates
we have already been confronted with are compositional
predicates. Thus cordateness and renateness are improper attributes
as the terms cordate and renate do not refer to real
attributes but to the fact of having component parts as a heart
and kidneys. X is cordate if X has a part Y (in a strict or
looser sense of having) which has the (proper or improper)
attribute of being-a-heart. Another kind of compositional predicate
is being-a-grandparent. If X is a grandparent of Z, there
is not really a direct relation of 'grandparenthood' between X
and Z (altho there may in practise be all kinds of other direct
relations between grandparents and their grandchildren). There
is a relation of parenthood between X (the fundament) and a
living being Y, and also a relation of parenthood between Y (the
fundament) and Z. It is these two relations which exist (unless
they happen to be no proper predicates themselves), not the
single relation of 'grandparenthood'. Especially when attributed
to people who are dead, (still-)having-a-great-influence is also
a compositional predicate. If X (still) has great influence (even tho
'e is dead), then, for example, X created
something Y --'e wrote a book or painted a picture, for instance-- and
many people who have come into contact with this creation Y
('er book or painting, or any copy thereof)
are (still) very much influenced by it now. The composition of
having-a-great-influence or fame, or for that matter infamy, may be much
more complex, but it is essential that it can always be reconstructed in
such a way that it consists of relations between terms which exist or
existed at the same moment or in the same period. Hence, there
is nothing mysterious about someone becoming famous or infamous
long after 'er death because (this kind of) fame or infamy itself
does, strictly speaking, not exist. X is famous or X is
infamous is in this case merely an abbreviation for a long
conjunction of propositions.
Predicates like cordateness, 'grandparenthood' and famousness
are conjunctive predicates: propositions in which they are
mentioned can be replaced by a conjunction of several propositions
in which only proper or more basic predicates are
mentioned. Compositional predicates for which this is not
possible might be called "sortal predicates". Some people,
especially metaphysical essentialists, maintain that species
membership is not just a question of having certain attributes
and/or relations in combination. They believe that sentences
with sortal predicate expressions such as <-- is a human being>
cannot be replaced by a conjunction of sentences with several
proper predicate expressions in them. Being-human would, then,
imply the presence of a certain specific structure of the body
called "human". Maybe, a being with predicates or parts A, B and
C would be human, but also a being with predicates or parts B, C
and D, and one with C, D and E. Solely having predicate or part
C would, then, not suffice to be called "human". (We shall
neither assume nor deny here that so-called 'sortal predicates'
are in fact a kind of conjunctive predicates.)
Instead of compositional, an improper predicate may also be
disjunctive. If X is p or X has (the attribute) P
means X has (the attribute) Q or (the attribute) R, then P is a
disjunctive attribute. An example of such an improper attribute
is concreteness if concrete means moving or at rest.
Being-at-rest or motionlessness is itself a proper predicate but
motion is in turn a disjunctive, improper predicate as there is
not just one predicate of motion but as many as there are speeds.
While we have been willing to accept the existence of abstract entities
such as attributes and relations, our realism now turns out to
be quite sober, for a great number of attributes and relations
for which there are names in everyday language are not proper
predicates and will not be regarded by us as existing in
reality. These nondeterminative, privative, disjunctive,
conjunctive or sortal 'predicates', which do not represent one
particular, existing attribute or relation at all, are mere
pseudo-entities.
|