1.7.4 |
THE DOMAIN OF A THING |
We use the word existing in such a way that at least
some predicative expressions of the language we communicate in
here do designate an 'existing' or 'real' attribute or relation.
Hence, attributes and relations, or --to be precise-- proper
attributes and relations, do exist. (In other words, there are
attributes and relations, namely proper attributes and relations.)
Moreover, given the special function of existence, the
existence of these predicates is language-independent. It does
not matter whether the language we use has a name for the
predicate in question or not, and it does not matter whether it
has a name for the predicate itself or for the (privative)
'fact' of not having the predicate in question. It is not
important either whether the predicate is mentioned in the first
or any higher-order domain of discourse: existence per se is
existence in the universe, and if mentioned, being mentioned in
the universe of discourse. We may only say that a certain thing
or predicate which exists, that is, exists in the universe (of
discourse) does not exist in a particular domain (of discourse).
Unlike existence, thingness is inherently domain-dependent
in that there is no thingness per se. For example, a primary
relation is no thing in the first or third domain of discourse,
whereas it is a thing in the second domain. Of course, one will
be tempted to say that a relation is always something, that is,
a thing, if it is existing, but this is only because by focusing
attention on the relation itself it is automatically located in
the second (or a higher-order) domain of discourse, where it is
indeed a thing. It is difficult, then, to transcend this
secondary (or higher-order) position and to look at the role of
primary relations in the first domain of discourse (or of any
kind of relation in the domain where it does relate things to
each other).
Where a relation relates it is nothing, that is, no thing
itself. In such a domain there is a relation between things or
not, but --again-- this relation itself, altho existing, is not
a thing. Only when the relation is derelativized does its existence
turn into thingness in the same domain of discourse, but
then it has become a kind of attribute. And when we subsequently
talk about the attributes and relations of relations themselves,
it is also in a derelativized form that they become things in
the next higher-order domain. Primary relations are therefore
things in the domain of which the basic things are secondary
attributes, that is, in the domain where they themselves are
related to other things by secondary relations.
In the first domain of discourse a nonbasic, primary thing
exists, is a thing ('something') and has a thing ('something':
at least an attribute and perhaps a component part). A proper,
primary attribute in this domain exists, and is also something,
but has no thing ('nothing': no part or attribute). A proper,
primary (nonderelativized) relation in this domain exists, but
is no()thing and has no()thing. A secondary or
higher-order predicate does not even exist in this domain, but as
existence is language- and discourse-independent, it does exist
nevertheless. The concepts of 'existing', 'being a thing' and 'having a
thing' are schematically represented in figure I.1.7.4.1 with
respect to their employment in the first domain of discourse.
In the second domain proper, primary attributes and relations
are nonbasic, secondary things which exist, which are something
and which have something, namely secondary attributes, and also
secondary relations with other secondary things. It is this
domain of discourse which bespeaks our special attention now.
|