2.3 |
OTHER PREDICATES FROM A CATENICAL PERSPECTIVE |
2.3.1 |
NONDETERMINATIVE PREDICATES |
When our knowledge about a particular thing is extended
by a new attribute or relation of which we are sure that the
thing concerned has it, this normally is a further determination
of its nature for us. The class of predicates for which this
does not hold is that of 'nondeterminative predicates'. Take,
for example, being a thing (or being-a-thing). This is an
'attribute' every thing in the domain of discourse has. Being
part of the universe cannot even be an attribute and is also
conceptually nondeterminative. Being classifiable and
collectable (in a set-theoretical sense) are of the same type.
Being itself (regardless of domain) or being a thing (in a
particular domain) is the common denominator for all
nondeterminative 'attributes' of this kind. Strictly speaking,
there is only one 'attribute' of being or existence: existentiality.
This is what all (existing) beings (which are things in some
domain) have in common. (As existence is something all beings
have in common --predicative or nonpredicative, primary, secondary
or whatever-- it is nonsensical to suggest that existence or
existentiality would be a first-order predicate or that it would
be of any other, definite order. Typical of existence is
precisely that it is of no particular, predicative order.)
A thing must always have 'the attribute of existence' if
such a universal pseudo-attribute is conceptually recognized.
It is something else, however, whether the idea or concept of a
thing denotes something in reality and whether a conceptual
combination of predicates, or predicates and parts, is a real
thing (rather than a mere set collected by its creator). The
thing one has in mind may, then, be an object or other nonbasic
thing, it may also be a predicate. Imaginary things (such as
gods, demons and other supernatural 'beings') are but too often
saddled not only with impossible combinations of predicates but
also with impossible predicates.
Attributes and relations which are predicated of a thing
while thinking about it, and which the thing would not have if
it were not conceived of, or had not been conceived of, are a
mere result of a person's own reflections on the thing in question.
The name we shall use for this type of nondeterminative predicate
is reflectional predicate. Reflectional predicates
are not determining for the things considered but for the
considerations, thoughts or reflections themselves. Being
thought of is a reflectional predicate, and so is being
denoted by an atomic expression in the language. (Other
examples have already been mentioned in 1.7.2.) Whereas,
theoretically, universal attributes such as the attribute of
existence belong to all (real) beings, members of the subclass
of reflectional predicates belong only to a certain category of
things. Thus being-collectable may be a universal attribute,
being-collected (in a general, set-theoretical sense) is a
reflectional predicate. And when collecting is used in a
concrete, everyday sense being-collected is even a determinative
primary predicate (or rather pseudo-predicate, as we will see).
To decide whether or not 'two' things are identical, one cannot
look at their universal attributes, because those attributes
are precisely what they are supposed to have in common as beings
or as things in the domain in question. And, altho one could,
one must not take their reflectional predicates into account
either when discussing the possible identity of 'two' things.
Even to be able to pose the very question itself one must have
given the 'two' things different names or descriptions to start
with. But 'having-the-name-a' or 'having-the-name-b' is
a reflectional attribute which is not determinative for the thing,
nor is 'being-written-' or
'having-one's-name-written-on-the-left-hand-side' and
'being-written-on-the-right-hand-side' with
respect to, say, a sign of equality (a = b). It is but too
easy to confuse distinctions in one's own reflections on reality
with distinctions, or rather the lack thereof, in reality
itself. Of course, distinctions in our thought are also
distinctions in reality. But then, they are distinctions in a
sort of propositional reality, not in the reality the thought
is about.
Like universal predicates, reflectional predicates do not
belong to any predicative order either. They cannot be classified
as first-order (being only the predicate of something that is
not a predicate itself), second-order (being only the
predicate of a first-order predicate) or higher-order, because
they simply are not real predicates of the thing conceived of. In
reality they stand for a predicate of the thinker
'imself, or of
'er thought, and as such they are
of the first predicative order but not as a reflectional attribute
or relation of the thing thought about. Whereas universal and
reflectional predicates belong to the category of nondeterminative
predicates, it is the category of determinative predicates in
which we find the primary, secondary and higher-order predicates
we have already been acquainted with.
|