5.2.3 |
THE GENERAL STRUCTURE UNDERLYING THE DIVERSE
NOTIONS |
It seems that theorists on relevancy have usually not
been familiar with the publications in other disciplines or
subdisciplines on the same subject. Or perhaps, they reasoned too
readily that 'their' relevancy had nothing to do with the
other notions of relevancy. If this were correct, however, we
could not explain very well how anyone when confronted with one
of these notions could ever have a less than vague, intuitive
idea about what a specific kind of relevancy (such as moral
relevancy) might denote -- and it is not said "connote". It is
hard to imagine that someone would treat truth in this way, and
suggest, for example, that scientific truth, pragmatic truth
and religious truth would all be entirely isolated, primitive
notions having nothing in common in denotation or connotation.
For again, if this were correct, no-one could even have the
vaguest, intuitive idea of what these phrases could mean if
'e
were confronted with them for the first time. Therefore there is
enough reason to assume some underlying structure -- a common
skeleton, albeit differently fleshed out for the several forms
of relevancy (and truth). Of course, we take it that the
underlying unity is to embrace more than some common positive
connotation of relevance and negative connotation of
irrelevance eagerly exploited in academic debate.
Let us take goal-dependent relevancy as a primitive notion,
as the prototype of all relevancy. Two entities are then related
if they are relevant in respect of the same goal (same in the
sense of identical). On this construction the notions of
symmetrical relevancy or relatedness are derivative and
presuppose the existence of ordinary, goal-dependent relevancy.
(Theoretically the relatedness might also be taken as primitive
and the common relevancy in respect of a certain goal as
derivative.) This conceptual picture 'explains' the reflexivity
of symmetrical relatedness, and shows also why nontransitivity
should be required. Pragmatic relevancy or practical relatedness
is from this point of view a particular kind of goal-dependent
relevancy, whereas semantic relevancy or relatedness
is a kind of (symmetrical) 'relevance-relatedness'. Pragmatic
relevancy in a narrow sense differs from other forms of
goal-dependent relevancy in that the fundament of the relation
is a speech-act; in a broad sense, in that the fundament is an
act in general. Semantic relevancy differs from other forms of
relevance-relatedness in that the entities related are propositions.
Given this sketchy representation of the overall structure in
which goal-dependent relevancy remains the basic notion, it is
easy to locate discriminational relevancy. Because of
the adjective it is the relevancy of a distinction, for example, on
the basis of age or nationality. The question is every time
whether the factor age or the factor nationality is
relevant in respect of something valued high, such as the (best) quality
of work to be done, or the (lowest possible) price of a ticket
to be paid. In questions of discrimination we are not just
interested in a statistical relevancy or other kind of symmetrical
relatedness between one distinction we could make and
another distinction we could make. We are interested in only one
distinction or cluster of distinctions at a time, and want to
know whether it is relevant with respect to a value which
those concerned have acknowledged as something to strive for.
The distinction itself is not defined as something to aim at
-- otherwise the question becomes superfluous. It follows that
the relevancy of discrimination is a kind of goal-dependent
relevancy with a distinction or cluster of distinctions as
relational fundament and a goal or other directional entity as
relational terminus.
Figure I.5.2.3.1 gives a schematic representation of most of
the conceptions of relevancy dealt with in the philosophical
literature in such a way that the general structure shows. All
these forms of relevancy mentioned in the literature have been
listed in figure I.5.2.3.2, as well as a few related relevancy
concepts. They are presented in such a way that it should become
clear on the basis of what characteristics they are primarily
(to be) classified. It goes without saying that this scheme is
an idealization. The actually used notions of relevancy are
often of a mixed character. Thus the primary classification of
discriminational relevancy may be on the basis of the type of
fundament (a distinction or set of distinctions) but this does
not mean that the criterions applied to the relation of
discriminational relevancy will not be equally typical. Similarly,
the primary classification of moral relevancy is on the
basis of the type of terminus (a moral goal or value), so it
seems, but the criterions of moral relevancy probably also
differ from those of all other forms of relevancy. The question
of what goal(s) moral philosophers actually choose, and of what
criterions they actually apply for moral relevancy (if any), is
not our present concern.
|