5.3.5 |
WHOLLY CONSEQUENTIALISTIC? |
In
chapter 7 of this book we will discuss several
types of normative-philosophical theories. We will then see that many
ethical philosophers distinguish consequentialist from deontological
(or other) theories. Consequentialism refers to the
theory that the ultimate standard of what is right or wrong is a
set of one or more nonmotivational values which are brought into
being. (Nonmotivational is added here to distinguish them from
values such as virtue, praiseworthiness and, perhaps, courage.)
Good and evil are defined in terms of these basic values
and an act is right, consequentialistically speaking, if, and only
if, it (or a rule under which it falls) produces, or is intended
to produce, at least as great a future balance of good over evil
as any available alternative. Deontology, on the other
hand, refers to a theory in which an action or rule is said to have
certain intrinsic right-making characteristics other than the
value it brings into existence, that is, other than its good or
bad consequences. (Deontology, which derives from deon,
that is, duty, is also defined in such a way that every ethical
theory which is not exclusively consequentialistic would be
'deontological', but this definition is not justifiable, neither
from a systematic nor from an etymological point of view.)
It is evident that a system of goal-dependent relevancy has a
plainly consequentialistic structure, especially when the focus
is a value such as the best quality of work to be done. Yet,
this does not mean that the goal(s) aimed at could not be of a
deontological nature, or be defined in deontological terms. For
example, if a theorist argues that it is a 'morally relevant
fact' that someone breaks
'er promise when
'e has entered into a
(quasi-)contractual obligation to pay, the fact in question is
relevant in respect of a 'deontic' goal, namely keeping one's
promise. Moreover, the relevancy is then obviously of the moral
type because of the very nature of the goal. As a deontic goal,
an obligation or duty can be represented by a variable (with at
least two values): 0 for not keeping one's duty, and 1 for
keeping it, or vice versa. Some moral philosophers might argue
that if at least one goal is of a deontic nature, the total
complex of relation and goal(s) --the superstructure with the
base on which it is erected-- is not (exclusively) consequentialistic.
The hidden premise in this argument is that the
descriptions of the actions deontic goals prescribe or forbid,
are not themselves value-dependent.
The question is whether any description of reality can ever
be given without that description being (believed to be)
relevant to a certain purpose. Someone would have to maintain
that this purpose is at least once of a deontic nature again. It
may also be that the deontologist's description of a certain
action or omission immediately depends on one or more nondeontic
goals. Take, for example, a party which is going to be attended
by a great number of people, and suppose that a particular
person has been invited to that party just like so many other
people. Now, suppose too that this person has told the host that
'e would come, but that 'e actually does not go, while having no
overriding (deontological) excuse for not going. The fact is
that because of the large number of people attending, the host
will hardly miss
'im, or not at all. There are people
--deontologists among them-- who would not call this "a case of breaking
a promise", but they obviously refrain from describing the
invited person's omission in this way, since 'er not doing what
'e said 'e would do does not harm anybody (or less than 'e would
harm 'imself by going). This interest in the absence of any harm
involved, or of minimizing the harm involved, is itself a
consequentialist consideration tho. This may also be the very
reason why in such a situation many people may not even expect
someone to necessarily do what 'e says 'e will do.
Both analytical and phenomenological thinkers have emphasized
how much the typification and description of reality depend on
what the one who does the description believes to be relevant.
The phenomenologist, for instance, may write that someone's
'types were formed in the main by others, predecessors or
contemporaries' and that the sum-total of the various typifications
constitutes a frame of reference in terms of which not only the
sociocultural but also the physical world has to be interpreted'.
This issue of the relevance of descriptions must play
an even greater part with respect to evaluative concepts. One
may, then, not simply presume anymore that, for example, (the
duty) not to steal is an (ultimately) deontological goal because
stealing is as value-laden as property is. As has
been pointed out in the previous chapter, the crux of the matter is
what kind of taking is, or should be described as, 'stealing'.
We shall not try to answer the question whether relevancy
also ultimately remains a consequentialist construct, even in
deontological theories. As we have not yet uttered a judgment on
the goal(s) (moral or not) one ought to choose, the answer to
that question is of little interest here. What is far more
interesting at this place is whether relevance is automatically
part of a normative system, if it is consequentialist (or insofar
as it is consequentialist). One such system is utilitarianism
in which the sole goal or ultimate value is (the maximization
of) happiness and/or the minimization of unhappiness.
Relevancy is, then, definitely not a (typically) utilitarian
concept, since it requires in no way happiness or utility to be a
focus of relevancy, let alone the only focus. But does a utilitarian
system by itself require relevance or --to be more
precise-- discriminational relevance with respect to happiness
or utility? We will see that if the promotion of utility, or the
likelihood of its occurrence is merely a question of the
correlation between an action or rule and a change of conditions,
a consequentialist system such as utilitarianism can collide
with requirements of discriminational relevance even tho utility
would be the sole focus of relevancy. This has indeed happened,
and particularly violently so when utility is not regarded as
the sole focus. To avoid it one must either add an independent
principle of discriminational relevance to the system --to say
nothing about one or more additional goals-- or incorporate this
principle into the definition of consequentialism, especially
into the meaning of bringing about or producing a value.
The question why correlation is no proof of discriminational relevance
in itself is one we will deal with in the next division.
|