7.2.2 |
PERFORMANCE, INTENTION AND MOTIVATION |
While the connection between concepts of one and the same
auxiliary dimension (like between good and bad) may
already cause problems, the connections between concepts of different
dimensions (like between wrong and vicious) may
even be more problematic and controversial. In order to deal with
these relationships we must have a clear picture, not only of what is
going on when a person acts, but also of what is going on when
'e decides to act. Too many
ethical theorists believe that moral agents base their judgments on the
facts of the moment and of the past, or even on future consequences.
Unfortunately they are mistaken in so thinking: instead, people base their
judgments upon personal information and presuppositions. (Let us
say: including their personal interpretation of the facts.) Not
only does a moral agent not literally base
'er judgment on the
facts, 'er conduct need not be rational or purposeful either: in
practise
it may be intuitive, emotional, impulsive or even antirational.
However, when a person does not just act like a
mere body would, we must assume that 'e has one or more goals or
objectives, and that 'e acts rationally or purposefully, thus
promoting or furthering 'er goal or objectives. This rational or
purposeful action is therefore determined by a goal (or objectives),
and information and presuppositions concerning the
relevant, factual and modal conditions.
From the point of view of rationality itself it does not
matter what someone's goal is. It may be any: one's own
well-being, somebody else's well-being, truth, deceit, and not
less any goal which in the eyes of 'sane' people would look
completely foolish or immoral. We need not be afraid of
propounding such a rational decision-theory, notwithstanding the
great antipathy many people feel towards anything that smells
of rationality. Presumably they feel so, because many 'rationalists'
embraced the wrong ultimate values and one-sided presuppositions,
not because there is anything incorrect with
rationality per se. One can rationally promote egoism and
equally rationally promote altruism. A moral rational decision,
however, is founded upon a (normative) value-theory (or
a 'theory of duty' or 'of right', if not accepted as part of a
value-theory). Such a theory tells the moral agent what kind of
situation is the better one and what are good-making features
(or right-making characteristics of duties to be fulfilled). The
theory to which the practical problems of the decision and
action themselves belong has been called "normative theory", but
this term is obviously far too broad, and we shall speak of
"(normative)" or "(moral) decision-theory". A
moral decision-theory presupposes --as has been said before
about this 'normative theory'-- 'some value-theory and derives
from it the requirements which it imposes on the behavior of individuals'.
Ideally speaking an agent acts in such a way that 'e furthers
the goal, or one of the goals, of the theory of value; that is,
'ideally speaking' from the value-theoretical point of view.
From this point of view it is performance which counts.
The relationship between rightness and goodness is then simply that
an action is right which promotes the good. (It does not follow
from this that an action can only be right if promoting what is
good.) In practise, however, the situation is often far from
ideal because the agent's information and/or presuppositions may
be wrong or insufficient, and it is on the basis of these that
'e has to decide what to do. Even
tho
the agent's intention may be to promote the good, or to
fulfil a certain duty,
'er actual performance may have very bad consequences, or may not result
in the fulfilment of that duty at all. From a decision-theoretical
standpoint the moral agent should not do what promotes the good
on the basis of the facts (which results in the right performance)
but what may be expected to promote the good on the basis of
'er own information and reasonable presuppositions. When
'e does act in such a way --and a rational moral agent cannot
do differently--, 'er action is the right one. Hence,
on the decision-theoretical level the relationship between rightness
and goodness has become more indirect, and from the performatory
standpoint it may even be said to be lacking, for an intentionally
right action may have bad consequences (or result in the
nonfulfilment of a duty). It is then wrong on the performatory
scheme, but can be excused on the intentional scheme.
Many acts can only be described within the framework of a
social institution. (If it is said "all acts", then (social)
institution is used in a very broad sense.) For example, voting
can only be described by referring to the whole formal system
within which it takes place; raising a hand or marking a piece
of paper is not voting by itself. Now, when judging acts or
abstentions from a decision-theoretical, moral position one must
take care that the information and presuppositions concerning
the particular act or abstention do not contradict the information
and presuppositions concerning the whole institution, and
participation or nonparticipation in that institution. It is a
value-theory in combination with information and presuppositions
concerning a particular act or abstention which determines
whether an act or abstention is right, and it is the same
value-theory which also determines in combination with other
information and presuppositions whether one should participate
in an institution, or whether the upkeep of that institution
itself is right.
But not only should the value-theory be the same for the act
and for the institution on which its definition depends, also
the information and particularly the presuppositions with regard
to the singular act and the whole institution should be such
that they can be rationally accepted by one agent on the basis
of one value-theory. And just as acts can be right on the
intentional level, yet wrong on the performatory level, so it
could be that a whole institution is normatively acceptable on
the basis of the agent's information and presuppositions about
it, yet unacceptable on the basis of the facts, or vice versa.
As illustrated in
figure I.7.2.2.1, this makes the situation
in decision-theoretical ethics clearly more complicated than in
performatory ethics. The decision-theoretical scheme is also
more realistic, however, as ethics is supposed to deal with the
conduct of persons, not just with the behavior of bodies.
Every value-theory has one or more axiomatic, normative
values (also called "nonmoral values" to distinguish them from
the 'moral values' which persons, groups of persons or elements
of personality are said to have). Being axiomatic, these
normative values are ultimate. Being ultimate, they are ends in
themselves which should not be treated as means to other ends.
However, when an agent intends to promote a value which is
ultimate in the value-theory concerned, it is not necessarily
the case that 'e promotes that value, or tries to promote that
value as an end in itself. It may be that 'e promotes it, because
the promotion of that value by
'imself is a means to another
end. That it is a means to another end does not imply that 'e
does not intend to promote it. On the contrary: if the promotion
of a certain objective will serve a higher goal, it is rational
to promote that objective, in spite of its not being ultimate.
We are thus faced with a contradiction: according to the
value-theory a certain value is ultimate, whereas the agent
treats it as a means to something else. That is why it is not
only the agent's performance and intention which count, but also
'er motivation. As regards ultimate values the agent's
intention should be 'er motive (and 'er performance should be what
'e intends to do). If so, then the motive is traditionally called
"virtuous" and the agent "not blameworthy" or, perhaps, "praiseworthy".
However, if the motive is detrimental to an ultimate
value, it is vicious and the agent blameworthy. (We will not go
into what it means that a motive is 'virtuous' in one respect
and 'vicious' in another respect, or neither virtuous nor vicious.)
The ethical profile now uncovered turns out to have three
successive layers or horizons: a performatory, an intentional
and a motivational one. The sharpest line in this profile is the
one which separates the performatory horizon (the 'A-horizon')
from the intentional horizon (the 'B-horizon'). The line between
the intentional and the motivational horizons (the 'B-' and
'C-horizons') is much vaguer. People (also ethical theorists) often
do not differentiate between intention and motive. In those
cases that it is indeed not necessary to do this, we ourselves
will speak of "(the) decision-theoretical (aspect of) ethics" as
contrasted with "its performatory aspect" or "performatory
ethics".
When endeavoring to locate the morality of doing (and also
the normativeness of being) in the ethical profile, we find
that it lies firm in the performatory horizon (without necessarily
being absent in the intentional horizon); when endeavoring
to locate the morality of being, we find it in the motivational
horizon. This, however, is not the sole difference between the two
forms of morality: the former starts in theory with individual
actions and their good consequences or right-making characteristics,
whereas the latter is not so much concerned with
one motive which prompted one action, but rather with long-term
motivational considerations. In an ethical doctrine based on
performance the good consequences or right-making characteristics
are believed to come first and moral value of character (or
'virtue') is made to depend on the right actions it promotes in
the long run; in an ethical doctrine based on motivation (or
'ethics of virtue') it is the motive which is believed to come
first, and the rightness of an act is made to depend on the
motive from which it was done. This 'motivism' --as it is also
called-- explains things back to front (a case of hysteron
proteron), but it is certainly meritorious for demonstrating to
us that there is also some worthwhile material lying beneath
the superficial layer of brute factual, modal and normative
elements.
A nonmotivist ethical doctrine which is not concerned about
the agent's intentions and motives at all is (purely)
performatory: it does not reach beyond the scope of the ethics of
performance. If it is also concerned about the agent's intention,
then it is (performatory-)intentional; and if also about
motives, then (performatory-)motivational. Both intentional
and motivational ethical doctrines are decision-theoretical. The
connection between the three horizons of the ethical profile
and the depth of nonmotivist ethical doctrines is shown in
figure I.7.2.2.2.
|