6.3.3 |
WITH CERTAIN QUALIFICATIONS |
After having reviewed some of the similarities, or
possible similarities, between the history and future of science
and the history and future of denominationalism, we should now
briefly consider some of the differences. The major difference
appears, then, to be one in the frequency of occurrences.
Whereas a scientific paradigm is supposed to span decades or
centuries, a denominational paradigm would span rather centuries
or millenniums. (This illustration is meant to be relative, for
both scientific and denominational paradigms might succeed each
other more frequently in the future. Moreover, whereas denominational
evolution may take a much longer time than scientific evolution,
it may be that political, or other specialist, ideological paradigms
span a much shorter time than those in science.)
The corollary of the difference of the role of the factor
time is that a denominational interparadigmatic period
(that is, the period between the heyday of the one paradigm and that
of the next) may be expected to last much longer than a
scientific interparadigmatic period, namely centuries instead of
decades. This explains why the community or society in question
may be multidenominational (bidenominational, for instance) for
a very long time. But even in this period its multidenominationalism
is a partial one: the old paradigm, now well beyond its
heyday and coexisting with alternative ideologies, still remains
the dominant one, even tho its dominance may eventually be one
in name only. However, in the denominational field a 'dominance
in name' is a form of 'real' denominational dominance because
of the symbolic aspect or emotive function of denominationalism.
From the point of view of ideological power, the adherents of
the old paradigm can allow the denominational pluriformity of
their community or society so long as no ideology emerges which
is to become a serious threat to the preponderant influence of their own
denomination -- threat not in terms of political
or military power, but in the sense of the force of its argumentation
and the appeal of its symbolism. In the centuries of
denominational instability (or 'interdenominationalism') preceding
the genesis of the ideology which is to become the new
paradigm, the influence of the old religion or other denomination
will perhaps wax and wane (dependent on the fashion of the
decade, so to say). But while its power may vary during those
centuries, it does remain in control until a radical denominational
change puts an end to its domination forever. The
hallowed tree which is hollowed out more and more by its own
factual-modal and normative anomalies is destined to finally
collapse under the confrontation with a new denominational
doctrine which has had enough time to reach maturity.
Now, it might be argued that, apart from times of crisis, the
nature of science presupposes general agreement about its
postulates, methods and findings, and that the nature of
ideology, and also of philosophy, presupposes the existence of
conflicting, ideological and philosophical views. Without opposing
parties there would be no controversial theories, and
ideology and philosophy would be 'science'; that is, ideology
and philosophy inclusive of denominationalism. On this assumption
it would not only be unnecessary that one denominational
paradigm succeeds another (after a long time of crisis, anomie
or multidenominationalism), it would even make such a paradigm
into a scientific one. Yet, as we have discussed in the previous
divisions of this chapter, a denominational doctrine or theory
has characteristics which a scientific doctrine or theory lacks
entirely, and vice versa, regardless of its being the sole
accepted one in a community or not. (Only philosophical theories
may perhaps receive the epithet scientific when they are
not contested any longer.) The analogy with science of single
denominational doctrines succeeding each other as dominant
paradigms of their era may therefore still hold, even tho the
ideological pluriformity would then only be found in the
instable period preceding the advent of a novel denominational
paradigm.
We should finally turn our attention to two important
features which distinguish a denominational doctrine in itself
from a scientific one, and see what bearing this has, or might
have, on the succession of, and attitude towards, denominational
paradigms in the past and future. The first one is the symbolic
aspect: a denominational doctrine is not just a plain collection of
plain assertions, coherent or not. In some way it also makes
an artistic use of symbols to convey the same message as the one
in the assertions. (As said before, some theorists call the
function of these symbols "emotive".) Let us include in this
'symbolism' everything not falling under that kind of verbal
communication which has to be interpreted literally. This
symbolism may therefore consist of the doctrine's literary way
of presentation, of visual and verbal symbols, or, for example,
of the observance of certain holidays, provided that these
symbols and holidays mean something because of the things they
represent.
It is not merely the presence of a system of symbols which
distinguishes a theodemonical or other denominational doctrine
from science; in practise it may also be the imposition
of such a system on whole societies or communities. If done, it is
evidently done as part of the total imposition of the theodemonical
or denominational ideology on the people concerned, but
symbolism plays a great part in bringing the 'glad tidings of
the word' (and, if the ideology is authoritarian, the sad
tidings of the sword). In a time of denominational upheaval the
system of symbols of what is later to become the new paradigmatic
doctrine may even be adjusted or extended in order to make it
more attractive to the majority of people who still adhere to
the old lights. To take a historical example: a theodemonist
religion competing for the place of the 'true faith' in the
denominational and political theater of a particular empire, may
not only decide to add the celebration of the birth of its
divine prophet to its symbolism, but even to move this very
birthday a couple of weeks back to make it coincide with a rival
theodemonist holiday which the general populace does not feel
like giving up. Being well aware that they otherwise would not
be able to beat the old paradigm of denominationalism, the
leaders of the novel system of theodemonism may thus find it
strategically necessary to incorporate some of the traditional
feasts, customs and rites into their own doctrine's symbolism.
Once they are accepted, however, they are disengaged from the
old denominationalism's substantive content and furnished with a
new meaning; that is, they are then presented to the community
as standing for the new denominationalism's own substantive
content.
The fact that symbols play such a significant role in denominational
theory and practise is at once a nuisance and an asset:
it is a nuisance as it makes it much harder to replace an old
denominational paradigm which is, or has become, inferior from
the scientific, philosophical and ideological point of view, but
perhaps not from an artistic point of view; it is an asset,
apart from esthetic considerations, because it enables an
alternative doctrine to establish itself as a new denominational
paradigm, even tho the general populace is not capable of
recognizing its superior normative and intellectual merits or,
dependent on the ideology concerned, lack thereof. This adds to
the theory of denominational paradigms a dimension which is
absent in the scientific field.
The second feature of denominationalism which fundamentally
distinguishes it from science is the normative aspect: like
every ideology, a denominational doctrine is a normative doctrine
which makes normative assertions, not just about utterances
and theories, but about the ground-world itself. (This is what
some theorists call "the imperative function of ideology".) It
follows from this aspect of denominationalism that the anomalies
of a denominational paradigm may not only be factual-modal, like
those of a scientific paradigm, but also normative. A factual-modal
denominational anomaly is, say, the 'explanation' of the
existence of two sexes by presenting the unsuspecting woman or
man with the image of a god violently sawing asunder single
beings into male and female, or, alternatively, taking a man's
spare rib and molding it into a woman. A normative anomaly is,
say, the image of a male supreme being commanding wives to honor
and obey their husbands (while not commanding husbands to honor
and obey their wives, for instance). These anomalies merely
serve as illustrations -- whether they are conceived of as
anomalies, and as important ones, may depend on the time when
they are considered. What is of paramount importance, however,
is that a denominational doctrine must make normative assertions
or have normative nonpropositional principles (since it is an
ideology) but need not make factual or modal assertions like a
scientific doctrine or theory. It is precisely these factual and
modal assertions which are subject to empirical falsification,
or which may later receive a certificate of extraordinary implausibility.
Hence, the analogy of the eternal succession of denominational
paradigms may even on a historicist account come
to an end with the emergence of a denominational doctrine which
does not venture its credibility by depending on empirical
suppositions with regard to the past, the present or the future.
The adherents of such a doctrine realize from the beginning on
that the part acted by denominationalism in disciplinary thought
is quite different from that of science. In this respect it is
the least scientific of denominational doctrines which has the
best chance of escaping the fate of a scientific paradigm.
There is one thing we can be sure about: the name of a
supernaturalist ideology with quasi-factual pretensions and
abominable prescriptions will not endure forever.
|