7 |
ELEMENTS OF NORMATIVE PHILOSOPHY |
7.1 |
ABOUT SAYING WHAT SHOULD BE |
7.1.1 |
ONTOLOGICAL AND EPISTEMOLOGICAL PRELIMINARIES |
An attribute or relation is a kind of secondary entity
(if not of a higher order) which a primary entity, like a
person, has (or had or will have), can have or should have; or
which it does not, cannot or should not have. If it has it, this
having of the predicate in question is a (specific) fact, that
is, a factual condition; if it can have it, a modal condition;
if it should or ought to have it, a normative condition. As explained
in section 3.1.3, the concept fact must be defined in
terms of a nonmodal, nonnormative is or has, and the
concept norm or normative condition in terms of a
nonfactual, nonmodal should (be/have). A 'normative condition'
is, then, a specific situation in which a universal or general 'norm'
applies. Neither norms nor normative conditions, or, for that
matter, modal or factual conditions, are entities in the first-
or second- or any higher-order domain of discourse. Thus, on our
ontology a normative condition does in no way resemble an
attribute or relation as existing in the second- or a higher-order
predicative domain. That is also why it is preferable to
speak of "auxiliary series" rather than of "catenas of factual
values" (that is, degrees of realization), "modal values"
(probabilities) and "normative values", each corresponding to
their own attribute or relation.
If something has a high value on the normative auxiliary
it may be called "normatively superior" or "good", and if
something produces a high or higher value, "right". It is
obvious that such a value, or 'goodness' or 'rightness', is not a
quality like tallness or any other primary attribute. If 'goodness'
is applied to a person or other primary thing, it does at
least play the same role as a primary attribute, but if it is
applied to attributes, relations or situations even that is not
the case.
Value (in the normative sense), goodness and
rightness have to be defined in terms of normative superiority, or
of a normative auxiliary. The connection is that something that
should be, should be had or should be done is itself normatively
superior or promotes what is normatively superior. One may also
reverse the definitions and define (normative) superiority
or should in terms of (normative) value or
goodness. Whichever way is preferred on this level of reasoning,
there is some conception involved which is incapable of definition. In
the factual sphere it is fact, (factual) value, degree of
realization or (factual) being which is equally incapable
of definition. This has been argued before, but with the use of the
wrong analogies.
We must start with noting that, while they belong to the same
auxiliary series, goodness and badness correspond to different
'values'. (Now using value in a general, auxiliary sense.)
When goodness is then compared with, for example, factual tallness,
this tallness corresponds to particular values of the
collection of a particular predicate catena. If the normative
auxiliary series has negative, neutral and positive values like
a catena, and if goodness corresponds to (a) positive value(s),
then goodness is normative positivity, and then its analog in
the factual sphere is factual positivity. Perhaps tallness is a
form of factual positivity, but it is not factual positivity
itself. The analog of factual tallness is not goodness but
normative tallness, that is, the normative condition (or 'fact'
in a loose sense) that something should be tall. Even if both
goodness and tallness were incapable of definition, it
would not be because they have the same status.
A major objection against goodness being indefinable like
redness or some other 'absolutely simple quality' is that
people do not all agree that certain objects are good in the way
they all agree that certain objects are red --and tall?--. There
is no test for value, it is said, like there is a test for fact.
The correct analogy, however, is not between tallness or redness
and goodness, but between the question whether a certain object
is tall or red, and the question whether it should be
tall or red. But, for the sake of argument let us agree that there
is a test for the former, and not for the latter. The kind of test
referred to is, then, one which makes use of 'absolutely simple'
observations, at least so far as a factual condition like that
of redness is concerned. Yet, even without these kinds of test,
people usually do have theoretical, ethical standards by which
they judge whether something should or should not be the case in
a moral sense. To arrive at such judgments it suffices to have
one or a limited number of general normative premises, but it is
indeed never possible to observe in a direct sense
whether something should or should not be the case, like it is
sometimes possible to directly perceive whether something is or
is not the case.
Ethical intuitionists would not agree with what is
averred here: they claim that what makes something good is a direct
sense or feeling on a person's part that it is so, or
--reformulated in terms of the triadic sphericity of reality--
what makes something as it should be is a feeling on a person's
part that it is as it should be. However, this sort of reasoning
which confuses the world with thoughts or feelings about the
world we must repudiate as we did several times before. Also
our position towards intuitionism is instrumentalistic tho: we
can live with the diehards of intuitionism who are not
willing to give up their belief. All we demand is that they intuit
the same as what we arrive at by thinking about it, and that they
accept that what we arrive at by reasoning is the same as what
we would have apprehended by intuition. Should they intuit
something different, while wanting to convince us nevertheless,
they will have to turn to reasoning as well, whether they like
it or not. (And since even mathematicians have given up the
belief in a priori concepts and self-evident truths, they had
better be prepared.)
|