Those who insist that property must be productive and
must have an economic function, should immediately agree that no
property may be spoiled in the hands of the owner. Labor
theorists have argued that property never can get big enough, so
long as the owner eats the fruits of
'er property before they
have rotted. (Luckily, such theorists of property cannot get
away with their spoil.) However, this does not leave the owners
with the unbearable burden of having to eat all the fruits of
their estates, or with the equally unbearable burden of having
to give away for nothing what they cannot eat themselves. The
solution is simple: barter away your plums for nuts. And then,
exchange your nuts, which will eventually wither too, for a
pretty piece of metal. Let then the community or the state
impress the shape of an official nut on it, and thou hast
'money'. It is this very money which human beings can keep
without spoiling and which they will take 'by mutual consent in
exchange for the truly useful but perishable supports of life'.
Such is the story of the birth of money in a nutshell; at least,
in one part of the world, for in other parts of the world it is
the shell which played the role of the nut.
As has been correctly pointed out, all limits on private
appropriation are made ineffective as soon as the above labor
theorists consent to the employment of money, which unlike plums
and land, can be accumulated without restraint. And altho it is
mentioned that money can be exchanged for the 'truly useful',
money has become an end in itself for but too great a host of people.
The nonproductive, nonfunctional, but nice things which can be done
with it, or which have to be forgone for it, play, then, no part
anymore. If
'e does not restrain
'imself, the bourgeois person
living under the natural-rights regime may thus become an
infinite appropriator suffering from one of the most unnatural
of diseases: 'acquisitis'.
Now, making money is one thing, believing that making money
has nothing to do with rights and duties, or morality, another.
There are those who indeed seriously maintain that making money
in business and acting morally are two different things which
are incompatible. In their eyes the pecuniary or financial could
and would be completely separated from the moral. This, of
course, is rubbish. Money inherently presupposes norms or
rights and duties. We have seen how money could only come into
existence because people (supposedly) had a right in
something, whether it be in their fruits, their nuts, their shells
or something else. And the exchange of the goods concerned (money
or otherwise) could solely take place by mutual consent. But this
requirement of mutual consent is a moral requirement since
those strong enough could just take what they wanted; they would
not need any money.
Without morality coins would hardly be worth their metal
content, and banknotes would hardly be worth the paper they are
printed on. It is only because of a promise to pay the bearer
in gold or other goods that bills in particular are of any
significance. And it is only because of people fulfilling their
duties, that is, their recognition of the rights of people
possessing the bills, that they are worth anything. Making
money does not mean making pieces of paper or metal in this
context; it means that a person will receive goods in return as
other persons keep their promises. The first 'person' to keep
'er promise in this respect is the government or agency by whose
authority the money is issued. If this agency does not take the
moral rights of the people who hold its banknotes and coins
seriously, and cannot be relied upon, then its money is plainly
worthless. (Obviously, this is not to say that a certain agency
might not be able to do what it ought to do.)
But granting that making money presupposes rights and duties,
could being paid in kind perhaps be wholly separated from acting
morally? No, it could not either. Only if people would transfer
goods at exactly the same moment from A to B, and from B to A,
could they do without any sort of explicit or implicit promise
and without any need of keeping promises. This kind of doing
business nonmorally would make business practically impossible
tho, modern business first of all. Except maybe for its most
primitive variant, business solely exists because of morality,
because of the acknowledgment of particular rights and duties.
The use of money which is so typical of doing business is the
use of it as a medium of exchange. The person who 'has' it, has
the right to use it as such, and to exclude nonowners from using
it in the same way. 'Having money' is thus in this sense merely
a kind of property, and therefore a sort of right.
The question remains: What is or are the most plausible
normative justifications for having a certain amount of money,
for claiming a right to an income, for not owning other people
or their bodies, and for being the sole proprietor of all parts
of one's own body?. This question must be tackled now, even
tho we cannot answer it here from an own
doctrinal, non-metadoctrinal
position, as we have so far merely acquired the most general and
abstract of instruments. Yet, we must have some idea beforehand
of what our property is in order to be able to proceed freely with
the work on our own system of disciplinary thought.
|