We have suggested that there is no universal,
noncatenical,
ultimate,
doctrinal
ground-world principle.
Isn't it equally plausible that there is no universal catenical, ultimate
principle either?
This would mean that, for example,
neutrality would be superior to
unneutrality one time, and that it would be inferior to extremity another
time.
And not only this: it would mean that one would have to strive for
neutrality on the basis of an ultimate principle one time, and that one
would have to strive for extremity on the basis of an ultimate principle
another time.
But why would neutrality be superior and have to be chosen as a
goal in the one case, and would extremity be superior and have
to be chosen in another? What would be the relevant difference
between the catenical aspects concerned? If there always is such
a relevant difference, the whole system of so-called 'ultimate'
principles boils down to one system with one ultimate principle
understood and interpreted in a relevantistic way. If the distinction
between aspects governed by different ultimate, catenical
principles is not always relevant, then the collection of these
principles is irrelevantistic and exclusivistic in its ground-world
effects. But such effects offend against
the norm of inclusivity.
A (positive) utilitarian would say that people ought to aim at
(non-happiness-catenary)
neutrality when this produces more
happiness than unhappiness. On the other hand, when it produces
more happiness than unhappiness to aim at extremity instead,
they ought to do that. (Aiming at the greatest happiness
possible is just such an example.) The relevance of the
distinction between aspects
--'e might claim-- is precisely
this: where (non-happiness-catenary) neutrality produces the
greatest utility, neutrality should be the goal; where some form
of unneutrality produces the greatest utility, this form of
unneutrality should be the goal. On this view there is only one
ultimate, catenary principle, namely that of the greatest
happiness. (For a negative utilitarian it is enough to minimize
unhappiness.) However, the utilitarian still has to demonstrate that
'er 'relevance' does
not depend on external nonrelevance, that is, that the distinction
'e draws between the happiness-catenary aspect and all other aspects in
'er selection of the ultimate principle is itself relevant.
Now, there are indeed good reasons to assume that the
position of the happiness
catena is a special one.
As a matter
of fact, we shall later take this special position of the
happiness catena into consideration ourselves. Yet, our choice
of an ultimate, catenical principle must not depend on such an
assumption, if only because an ultimate principle of happiness
would discriminate between primary things which are
happiness-catenal
and primary things which are not. Moreover, a sole,
ultimate principle of happiness would not be compatible with our
neutralistic interpretation of the principle of discriminational
relevance. A utilitarian interpretation of this principle would
make equality and nondiscrimination in the inclusivistic sense a
contingent matter. Therefore, the sole, ultimate, catenary
principle is not the extremist principle of (the greatest)
happiness or utility. That principle is not even truly catenical,
because it is merely concerned with one catena in particular,
and not with catenas in general.
Given that our equal, unless interpretation of the principle
of discriminational relevance is egalitarian, that is,
neutralistic, there is only one ultimate, catenical principle
which is compatible with it; and that is the principle of
neutrality. Solely the relevantistic-egalitarian formulation of
the norm of inclusivity is in keeping with our sense of justice,
and therefore this egalitarianism or neutralism with respect to
the making of distinctions is certainly a very important reason
for universal neutralism. (Equality itself could not be conceived
of as an ultimate principle, for this would require a
justification of the distinction between difference-catenary and
other catenical aspects.)
To make it plausible
tho that
neutrality is ultimately indeed superior to polarity, at least as a
basic rule to start from, more examples are needed. Of course,
counterexamples which seem to make this principle implausible
can be adduced too. Thus, not only unhappiness is normatively
inferior on the principle of neutrality, but also happiness when
compared with a neutral state of being neither happy nor
unhappy --the crucial presupposition being that all other things
are equal. Such apparent counterexamples we will deal with
later in this chapter (in
3.4).
Besides the egalitarian argument for the superiority of
neutralness, there is a systematic, catenical argument. It is
that the neutrality is not just a predicate of the catena but
a special and central one. Suppose that the highest normative
value were assigned to an unneutral proper predicate, then the
first arbitrary choice would be between a negative and a
positive predicate, and the second arbitrary choice would be
the degree of negativity or positivity. For a nonderivative
catena it does in itself not matter which side is called "the
negative" and which side is called "the positive one". To argue
that it is '(most) logical' to consider positivity superior and
negativity inferior, is tantamount to arguing that what is
superior and what is inferior might as well have been the other
way round. This is not the sort of guideline one would expect
from a normative doctrine. Nonetheless, one might still wonder
why a predicate (or the thing having it) would be more inferior
as it becomes more unneutral or extreme. Could not the neutrality
be superior, while all unneutral proper predicates would be
equally inferior? Such an evaluation would imply that
being-perineutral
or being-extreme made, normatively speaking, no
difference. But especially where the neutrality principle provides
the goal to aim at, it makes an enormous difference
whether something or someone aims at perineutrality, rather than
at extremity, and hardly any difference whether it or 'e aims at
perineutrality, rather than at neutrality. From this angle it
must therefore be assumed that not only neutrality is superior
to unneutrality, but also perineutrality to non-perineutral
unneutrality, and nonextreme unneutrality to extremity.
A third argument in favor of neutrality is the hypothesis of
mean-neutrality as it is actually assumed to be true in
scientific theories. As explained in the Book of Instruments
(I.2.6.3) this hypothesis underlies
the principle of the conservation
of mass and energy and similar, physical principles of
conservation. (Principles is to be preferred to laws as
principles does not presuppose a supernatural lawgiver.) It is
because the mean energy increase in a closed system has to be,
or is taken to be, 0 that no energy will melt into, or spring
from, nothingness. (If the system is called "closed" altho
'energy' may flow in and out, it is the mean increase of mass
which is 0.) The fact that for every process the decrease of
electrical charge is the same as the increase of charge agrees
with this hypothesis as well. Other principles of conservation
are those of rotation and momentum. In all these cases the total
amount of the quantity concerned does not change, or --to put it
differently-- the quantity is 'conserved'. The conservation
principles in these interactions are immediately related to the
catenical symmetries in the predicates of the interacting bodies
or particles. That is why physicists tend to use the notions of
symmetry (or the symmetry of a process) and conservation
(or the principle of conservation) interchangeably. These two
notions together express the regularities in the subatomic world
of particles and antiparticles between which there is such a
basic symmetry. The search for an 'ultimate, fundamental symmetry'
in nature is therefore nothing else than a search for the
last principles of conservation and the common denominator of
all of them.
A different type of argument in favor of neutrality does not
so much center on states of constancy or neutrality, but on
attempts or forces to attain neutrality and to maintain delicate
balances in nature. Altho there is no logical connection between
these descriptions and the normative principle of neutrality
--like there is no logical connection between facts and any
normative principle--, they put neutrality in a greater perspective
and narrow the gap between processes initiated by persons
for normative reasons and processes occurring in nature which
are not intentional but aimed at the same good nevertheless.
Induction currents, for instance, work against the change by
which they came into existence. The very attraction between
positively charged particles on the one hand, and negatively
charged ones on the other, and the repulsion of entities of the
same polar kind, is a phenomenon which contributes to electroneutrality
in general. Furthermore, if the external conditions
of a system in equilibrium (as concentration, pressure, temperature)
are changed, the balance will shift in such a way that the
change introduced will be leveled as much as possible. (The
neutral or neutral-directed concepts here are equilibrium,
balance and leveling; the unneutral concept is change.)
In thermodynamics it is a principle (or 'law') that every system
which can take its own course aims at maximum entropy. Now,
entropy is a tricky physical notion which may be defined in
several ways, dependent on the quantity or dimension the
theorist is most interested in. 'E may think of it in terms of
unavailable energy in a closed system, or in terms of 'chaos' or
'disorder' because of the movement of matter in chance patterns.
Yet, however irregular the movement of individual molecules may
be, the maximum entropy of the system as a whole is a state of
overall uniformity or homogeneity. In this state the concentration
is the same in all subsystems, that is, the same as the
mean one for the entire system. For the system as a whole,
maximum entropy corresponds to a complete chemical equilibrium
and the greatest order possible in that the density is the same
throughout. It is this order the system aims at, and which
remains once it has been attained.
There are numerous other phenomena which demonstrate that the
whole world is fully alive with a quest for neutrality.
Particularly in biology there is an abundance of examples of
living beings or ecosystems which try to restore every balance
upset. Tho an act in quest of neutrality in one respect may
conflict with an act in quest of neutrality in another respect,
the fact that 'nature' itself, to which any ideology is alien,
has always known some principle of 'neutrality', of 'equilibrium',
of 'harmony', or whatever it should be called, makes
the cultural selection of such a principle a well-considered and
inspiring choice. But perhaps this natural 'canon of equilibrium'
is not a principle we can really draw from nature.
Maybe it is merely neutralistic imagination or a prejudgment. The
principle of conservation does not seem to hold for all physical
quantities, and there are also enough examples of the destruction
of natural equilibriums.
As mentioned in the Book of Instruments
(4.3.1) it has been suggested
that it is people who prescribe the laws of science to nature.
(And for so-called 'laws' this is quite obvious.)
There is one thing, however, which we certainly do not
prescribe to nature but to ourselves. That is, that it is the
absence of neutrality which requires our explanation or justification
more than anything else, and that it may even suffice to
explain or justify polarity by referring to a neutrality of
another aspect, or to a striving for such a neutrality.
Conservation, symmetry and equality are explanations, justifications
or goals in themselves, both in the field of natural
science and in the field of the normative. In everyday life,
too, it is considered rational to start from the assumption that
the chance that one thing will occur is the same as the chance
that another thing will occur, until or unless one has good
reasons to suppose that the one chance is bigger than the other.
Indubitably, this general attitude towards neutral notions like
equality and symmetry is im- or explicitly founded in a
neutralistic postulate.
|